PERSONS (Project towards partial fulfilment of the internal assessment in the subject of Jurisprudence)
Submitted by:
Submitted to:
Jai Sahai Endlaw (Roll No. 643)
Dr. Mononita Das
Manish Parmar (Roll No. 646)
Assistant Professor
Riyaz Bhagat (Roll No. 658)
Faculty of Law
Siddhant Kant (Roll No. 612)
Semester VIII
National Law University, Jodhpur Summer Session (January – May 2012)
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Acknowledgement…………………………………………………………………….……….2
Research Methodology………………………………………………………………………...3
Introduction……………………………………………………………………………………5
Chapter 1: Basic Concepts……………………………………………………………....…….6
Chapter 2: Theories……………………………………………………………………………8
Chapter 3: Corporate Personality…………………………………………………………….18
Conclusion……………………………………………………………………………………22
References……………………………………………………………………………………24
1
ACKNOWLEDGEMENT
We would like to thank our Jurisprudence teacher Dr. Mononita Das, for her constant support and guidance. First of all, we would like to thank her for giving us an opportunity for doing a project on this topic. Secondly, we would like to thank her for guiding us throughout and making our path clear when we were in doubt. She not only cleared our doubts but also made us learn with each further step that we took in this project. Next, we would like to extend our gratitude towards the engineers of the university for providing us a round the clock access to the Internet without which this research could not have taken a concrete form and also the library staff which proves to be the lifeline of any academic work.
2
RESEARCH METHODOLOGY
Subject: Jurisprudence Topic: Persons Broader area: Personality Objective: The objective of this paper is to provide a detailed analysis of the views expressed by different jurists regarding the concept of „persons.‟ This endeavour showcases the basic concepts related to personality and further expounds on various jurists‟ theories regarding the nature of „legal persons.‟ It also deals with the concept of corporate personality and the concepts enunciated by Sir John Salmond and Max Weber. Each chapter in this project aims to study and develop the theory relating to „persons‟ as considered by the common law jurists and examples of the same available in Indian jurisprudence. On the whole, the researchers have tried to show the gradual change in perception of this philosophy and how the Courts in India have perceived it. The legal concept of personhood is one of the most fundamental ideas and has been the subject of many discussions and theories. Further, the implications it has for the evolution of purposeful jurisprudence can only be described as significant. The analysis in this paper attempts to cover the most important teachings on the topic as well as examine the surrounding historical, sociological and political facets so as to arrive at an accurate understanding of the topic. Research Questions: 1. What are the different kinds of „persons‟ recognized by Jurists? 2. What are the various theories given by Jurists regarding „persons‟? 3. How have these theories expressed by Jurists changed with passage of time? 4. What is Corporate Personality? 5. How is Corporate Personality perceived in India?
3
Geographical Indications: The scope of this research paper is limited to British and Indian jurisdictions as the Jurists studied in the course of this paper have restricted their views to these jurisdictions. Temporal: Not applicable Sources: 1. Library, National Law University, Jodhpur 2. World Wide Web Chapterisation: Chapter I: Basic Concepts The difference between natural persons and legal persons is provided. Further, the difference between the „status‟ and „capacity‟ of a person is examined. Status of unborn persons is differentiated between Common law and Indian jurisprudence. The views of Salmond, Gray and Dr. Allen are discussed and compared.
Chapter II: Theories Various theories of Jurists such as Brinz, Barker, Ihering, Duguit, Hohfeld, Savigny, Salmond, Kelsen and Gierke are examined. Their theories are examined and the gradual change in perception is noted from a restricted view to a much more liberal view. An analysis of various concepts having their origin in Roman and English law is carried out in this section.
Chapter III: Corporate Personality Salmond and Weber‟s views on corporate personality are compared. The Indian perspective on Corporate Personality is examined through the Supreme Court and High Court decisions in various cases relating to the nature of Idols and Funds, Coparcenary system and State as a juristic person.
4
INTRODUCTION The legal use of the word person has attracted an assortment of theories which is probably second to none in volume. Before turning to them, it is necessary to have an idea of the way in which various problems that have arisen in this connection are dealt with, and what part the term person plays in relation to them. The word has undergone many shifts in the meaning, so two questions have to be asked: how has it been used? And, how does it function?1 With regard to its uses, it might be noted that originally it meant a mask, then the character indicated by a mask, the character in a play, someone who represents a character, a representative in general, representative of the church, a parson.2 In Roman law another shift of meaning seems to have occurred from a character in a play to any human being. The development of such capacities and bodies, such as municipium and the collegium, may have helped to abstract the idea. Despite this it would be wrong to suppose that the word persona was used in any technical sense in Roman law: there was only a tendency in that direction in late law.3 Some such idea seems to have been presenting the mind of Tertullian, who brought the legal ideas to bear on the interpretation of the „person‟ of Christ, which gave the word another shift in meaning as connoting the „properties‟ of divinity and humanity.4 English law has taken over the popular reference of the word to human beings with all its emotive overtones, but the legal significance centres on the jural relations that are focused on an individual. This represents a technical shift in the meaning „person‟. The law has gone still further and applied it to corporations, which is yet another a technical shift and does not rest on any similarity, pretended or real, between human beings and groups. One may acknowledge that a group is a unit without feeling impelled to call it a person; which indeed is the case with unincorporated associations. Had the law stopped at human beings in its use of the word „person‟ a good deal of needless perplexity would have been avoided. As a unit of jural relations, however, the term has lent itself to applications other than to human beings and hence serves different functions.
1
Hart, „Definition and theory in Jurisprudence‟ (1954) 70 LQR 37
2
Greenough and Kittredge Words and their ways in English speech p 268, quoted by Ogden and Richards The Meaning of Meaning p 129. 3
Duff Personality in Roman private Law ch. 1
4
Bethune-Baker An introduction to the Early history in the Christian doctrine ch. 10
5
CHAPTER 1 BASIC CONCEPTS Persons, so defined are of two kinds and are distinguishable as natural and legal. Natural person means a human being. It denotes a person not fictional or legal.5 Legal Persons on the other hand are beings real or imaginary. They are persons by a figment. For the purposes of legal reasoning they have been treated in greater or smaller degree in the same way as human beings. NATURAL PERSONS The only natural persons are human beings. But in ancient times, all human beings were not granted legal personality. The case of the slave is well known that they were treated no more than the mere chattels. Similarly, a person who takes a religious or holy order or enters a monastery has in certain systems been treated as civilly dead. In Hindu society too, when a person becomes a sannyasi his proprietary rights turn off and his property goes to his heirs as if he were dead. At one time, human beings who had been declared outlaws were not regarded as persons in the eyes of the law and killing them was not homicide. Lunatics, new born babies and infants have however been said to have limited and restricted rights. They do not possess as many civil rights as normal human beings have. Though in modern times it has been the tendency to grant legal personality to all living within the territory of the State, the most systems however provide a rule that wheresoever‟s legal personality is granted it begins with birth and ends with death. LEGAL PERSONS A legal person is any subject matter other than a human being to which the law attributes personality. This extension, for good and sufficient reasons of the conception of a personality beyond the class of human beings is one of the most noteworthy feats of the legal imagination. The law, in creating legal persons, always does so by personifying some real thing. There is, indeed, no theoretical necessity for this, since the law might, if it is so pleased, attribute the quality of personality to a purely imaginary being and yet attain the ends for which this fictitious extension of personality is devised. Personification, however, conduces so greatly to simplicity of thought and speech that its aid is invariably accepted.
5
Austin, Lectures on Jurisprudence, 3rd ed, Campbell, London, 1869, pp. 357-358
6
The thing personified may be termed the corpus of the legal person so created. It is the body into which the law infuses the animus of fictitious personality. To be a legal person is to be the subject of rights and duties. To confer legal rights or to impose legal duties, therefore, is to confer legal personality.6 Among definitions to be found in discussions of the subject, perhaps the most satisfactory is that legal personality is the capacity for legal relations, but legal philosophers and students of jurisprudence have not been content with so simple an explanation. They have sought for the "internal nature" of legal personality, for an abstract essence of some sort which legal personality requires. Thus Gray thinks there can be no right, and therefore no legal personality, without a will to exercise the right. "That a right should be given effect," says he, "there must be an exercise of will by the owner of the right."7 But, after having adopted the premise that a will is of the essence of a right, he then proceeds to explain how it is that certain human beings without wills and even inanimate objects do have legal personality, a task which he complains is the most difficult "in the whole domain of Jurisprudence."8 Salmond, on the other hand, discovers a different quality which, by his definition, is essential to a right. "No being is capable of rights," says he, "unless also capable of interests which may be affected by the acts of others," and "no being is capable of duties unless also capable of acts by which the interests of others may be affected."9 But Salmond's pre- supposition of an intrinsic essence does not give him as much trouble as did Gray's, for no sooner has he discovered the necessity of an interest to the existence of a right than he also discovers that the same act of investiture which attributes the right also attributes the interest. He defines a legal person, therefore, as "any being to whom the law attributes a capacity of interests and, therefore, of rights, of acts and, therefore, of duties."10
This is substantially the same
conclusion Mr. Gray reached with respect to the necessity of a will. Where there is no will in fact the law attributes one. So long as it has unlimited power of attribution, neither theory need hinder the sovereign in bestowing legal personality upon whomever or whatever it will.
6
Gray, The Nature And Sources Of The Law (2d Ed. 1921) 27
7
Salmond, Jurisprudence (5th Ed. 1916) 272
8
Holland, Jurisprudence (9th Ed. 1900) 88
9
Ibid
10
Pollock, A First Book of Jurisprudence (1923) 114.
7
The first class of legal persons consists of corporations, those which are constituted by teh personification of groups or series of individuals. The individuals who thus form the corpus of the legal persons are termed its members. The second class is that in which the corpus or object selected for personifications not a group or series of persons but an institution. The law may if it pleases regard a church, or a hospital, or a university, or a library as a person. That is to say it may attribute personality not to any group of persons connected with the institution but to the institution itself. The third class of legal person is that in which the corpus is some fund or estate devoted to special uses – a charitable fund, for example, or a trust estate or the property of a dead man or incorporation. If it chooses to personify at alit personifies not the fund or the estate but the body of persons who administer it. Yet the other way is equally possible, and may be equally expedient. The choice of the corpus into which the law shall breathe the breath of a legal personality is a matter of form rather than substance. HUMAN BEINGS Individual are the social units and pre-existed both laws and society. Since laws are made by them and for them, and since jural relations are relations between individuals, it is no wonder that the jural relations of each individual came to be one of the first and most important unities for legal purposes.11 The legal concept of a human being as a person is simply a multitude of claims, duties, liberties etc. treated as a unit; as such there is no distinction in law between „natural‟ and „legal‟ persons12
11
Slavery in England died out before Norman times. The attribution of rights or responsibility to animals has likewise long been obsolete. The responsibility of animals in common in primitive systems: Exodus xxi 28; XII Tables 8.8: Dg.1.1 pr. In English law the responsibility of wrong doing things, deodand, was abolished by statute in 1846. Though the institution had long been obsolete. The Privy Council had occasion to deal with the position of an idol in Hindu Law, Pramatha Nath Mullick v Pradyumna Nath Mullick (1925) LR 52 Ind App 245. 12
Cf Kelsen General theory of Law and State pp 93 et seq; Pure theory of Law (trans M Knight) p 173.
8
STATUS V. CAPACITY Personality may be distinguished from status and capacity. Status is a word which has no precise meaning. Salmond13 has however given four meanings of the word. a) Legal condition of any kind whether personal or proprietary b) Personal legal condition excluding proprietary relations c) Personal capacities and incapacities as opposed to other elements of personal status d) Compulsory as opposed to conventional legal position. Austin14 agreed that the term cannot be used with exactness but thought that when for ease of exposition it is useful to separate a complex of rights and duties of capacities and incapacities which specifically affect a narrow class, it is convenient to designate that complex by the term status. Dr. Allen15 says that status may be described as the fact of condition of membership of a group of which the powers are determined extrinsically by laws status affecting not merely one particular relationship but being a condition affecting generally though in varying degree a member‟s claims and powers. It is not merely a basis for short, status is a condition which arises due to the membership of a class or group and affects the rights and duties of the members of that class. A person may have a number of status at the same time, for example he might be a husband, father and an officer. The general principle of status is that when created by the law of one country it is or ought to be judicially recognized as being the case everywhere, all the world over.16 Dr. Allen distinguishes between status which is a condition and capacity which is a power to acquire and exercise rights and the rights themselves which are acquired by the exercise of that capacity. Capacity in other words means the rights and powers of a person by virtue of his being in a particular position. Law recognizes different capacities in which a man may act. Thus if a person is a judge, he has the capacity of a judge as well as the capacity of a 13
Salmond, Jurisprudenec, 12th ed, p. 240
14
Jurisprudence, ii. 687
15
Allen, Legal Duties, 28
16
Re Luck‟s Settlement Truses, (1940) 1 Ch. 864 at p. 889, Per Scott., LJ
9
citizen at the same time. But the mere fact that a man has double capacity does not mean double personality. His legal personality is only one. Therefore a person in one capacity cannot enter into a contract or any other like transaction with himself in his other capacity. THE LEGAL STATUS OF UNBORN PERSONS Thought the dead possess no legal personality, it is otherwise with the unborn. There is nothing in law to prevent a man from owning property before he is born. His ownership is necessarily contingent, indeed, for he may never be born at all; but it is none the less a real and present ownership. A man may settle property upon his wife and the children to be born of her. Or he may die intestate, and his unborn child will inherit his estate. Yet the law is careful lest property should be too long withdrawn in this way from the uses of living men in favour of generations yet to come; and various restrictive rules have been established to this end. No testator could now direct his fortune to be accumulated for a hundred years and then distributed among his descendants. A child in its mother‟s womb is for many reasons regarded by a legal fiction as already born, in accordance with the maxim Nasciturus pro jam nato habetur. In the words of Coke: “The law in many cases hath consideration of him in respect of the apparent expectation of his birth.” Thus, in the law of property, there is a fiction that a child en ventre sa mere is a person in being for the purposes of 1. The acquisition of property by the child itself 2. Being a life chosen to form part of the period in the rule against perpetuities17 To what extent an unborn person possess personal as well as proprietary rights is a somewhat unsettled question. Wilful or negligent injury inflicted upon a child in the womb by reason of which it dies amounts to murder or manslaughter.18 The rights of an unborn person, whether proprietary or personal are all contingent on his birth as a living human being. The legal personality attributed to him by way of anticipation falls away ab initio if he never takes his place among the living. Finally, though the law imputes
17
Winfield “The Unborn Child” (1942) 5 Univ. Of Toronto Law Journal 278 at 279
18
R v. Senior (1832) 1 Moody C.c. 344; R v. West (1848) 2 Car. & Kir. 784
10
no rights to persons not yet even conceived, it may protect their interests. If some of the beneficiaries of a trust are unborn persons, the trust cannot be varies without obtaining the court‟s consent on their behalf. In India too, the Principle laid down in Tagore v. Tagore19 that a person to be entitled to take under a will must be in fact or in contemplation of law be in existence at the time of the testators death, has apparently been alrtered by the three acts viz. The Hindu Transfers and Bequests Act, 1914; Hindu Disposition of Property Act, 1914; Hindu Transfers and Bequests (City of Madras) Act, 1921 with the result that bequests can be made t unborn persons subject to the limitations and provisions contained in Ss.113-116 of the Indian Succession Act, 1925.
19
(1872) Beng. LR 377
11
CHAPTER II THEORIES ON THE NATURE OF ‘LEGAL PERSONS’ Professor Wollf has observed that on the Continent legal writers may be grouped into two categories; those who have written on the nature of the Legal persons and those who have not yet done so.20 In dealing with some of these theories it is as well to bear in mind that the attitude of the law has not been consistent and also that there is a distinction between appreciating the unity of a group and the way the word „person‟ is used.
PURPOSE THEORY This theory, that of Brinz primarily, and developed in England by Barker21, is based on the assumption that „person‟ is applicable only to human beings; they alone can be the subjects of jural relations. The so-called „juristic‟ persons are not persons at all. Since they are treated as distinct from their human sub-stratum, if any, and since jural relations can only vet in human beings, they should be regarded simply as „subjection properties‟ designed for certain purposes. It should be noted that this theory assumes that other people may owe duties towards these „subjection properties‟ without there being correlative claims, which is not impossible, although critics have attacked the theory on this ground. As applied to ownership, the idea of the theory was designed mainly to explain the foundation, the Stiftung of German law. And it would also explain the vacant inheritance, the hereditas jacens, of Roman law. It is not applicable to English law. Judges have repeatedly asserted that corporations, for instance are „persons‟, and it is in this use of the word that need explaining. If they say that these are persons, then to challenge this usage would amount simply to using the word differently from Judges. To Duguit „purpose‟ assumed a different meaning. To him the endeavour of law in its widest sense is the achievement of social solidarity. The question is always whether a given group is pursuing a purpose which conforms with social solidarity. If it does, then all activities falling
20
Wolf „on the nature of legal persons‟ (1938) 54 LQR 494.
21
Brinz Lehrbuch der Pandekten 1. Pp 196-238; III, pp 453-586; Barker in his translation of Gierke Natural Law and the Thoery of Society Ixxiii-Ixxxvii.
12
within that purpose deserve protection. He rejected the idea of collective will as unproven; but there can be, he said, a collective purpose.22
THEORY OF ENTERPRISE ENTITY Related, though somewhat removed from the above discussed theory, is the theory of the enterprise entity. The corporate entity, it is said, is based on the reality of the underlying enterprise23. Approval by law of the corporate from establishes a prima facie case that the assets, activities and responsibilities of the corporation are part of the enterprise. Where there is no formal approval by law, the existence, and extent of responsibility and so forth of the unit are determined by the underlying enterprise. This way of looking at it does explain the attitude of the law towards unincorporated associations and also leaves room for the miscellaneous situations in which corporate unity is ignored. The theory is a utilitarian one.
SYMBOLIST OR BRACKET THEORY According to Ihering the members of a corporation and the beneficiaries of a foundation are the only persons. „Juristic person‟ is but a symbol to help in effectuating the purpose of the group, it amounts to putting a bracket round the members in order to treat them as a unit. This theory, too, assumes that the word person is confined to human beings. It does not explain the foundations for the benefit of mankind generally or for animals. Also- and this is not so much as an objection as a comment- this theory does not purport to do more than to say what the facts are that underlie propositions such as, „X and Co.‟ owe Y certain amount of money. It takes no account of the policy of the Courts in the varying ways in which they use the phrase. „X and Co.‟; whether they will, for instance, lift the mask, i.e. remove the bracket, or not. Closely related to this theory is that of Hohfeld, which may be considered next. .
22
Duguit The progress of continental law in the 19th century. Pp 87-100
23
Berle „The theory of enterprise entity‟(1947) 47 Columbia Law Review 343; Lord Wilberforce in British Railway Board v Herrington [1972] AC 877 at 911, 922 [1972]1 All ER 749 at 769, 779; DHN Food Distributers ltd. v Tower Hamlets London Borough Council [1976] 3 All ER 462, [1976] 1 WLR 852.
13
HOHFELD‟S THEORY Hohfeld24 drew a distinction between human beings and „juristic persons‟. The latter, he said, are the creation of arbitrary rules of procedure. Only human beings have claims, duties, powers and liabilities; transactions are conducted by them and it is they who ultimately become entitled and responsible. There are, however, arbitrary rules which limit the extent of their responsibility in various ways, e.g. to the amount of the shares. The „Corporate person‟ is merely a procedural form, which is used to work out in a convenient way for immediate purposes a mass of jural relations of a large number of individuals., and to postpone the detailed working out of these relations among the individuals inter se for a later a more appropriate occasion. This theory is purely analytical and like the preceding one, analyses a corporation out of existence. Although it is reminiscent of a person who fails to see a wood and sees onlu a collection of trees, it would be unfair to suggest that Hohfeld was advocating that corporations should be viewed in this way. He was only seeking to reduce the corporate concept to ultimate realities. What he said was that the use of the group terminology is the means of taking account of mass individual relationships. It is to be noted. However, that he left unexplained the inconsistencies of the law; his theory was not concerned with that aspect of it. Finally, to say that corporate personality is a procedural form may seem to be rather a misleading use of the word „procedural‟. What seems to be meant is that the unity of a corporation is a convenient way of deciding cases in court.
KELSEN‟S THEORY Kelsen25 began by rejecting, for purposes of law, any contrast between human beings as 'natural persons' and 'juristic persons'. The law is concerned with human beings only in so far as their conduct is the subject of rules, duties and claims. the concept of 'person' is always a matter of law; the biological character of human beings is outside its province. Kelsen also rejected the definition of person as an 'entity' which 'has' claims and duties. The totality of claims and duties is the person in law; there is no entity distinct from them. Turning to corporations, he pointed out that it is the conduct of human beings that is the subject matter of 24
Hohfeld Fundamental Legal Conceptions chs 6 and 7.
25
Kelsen General theory of law and State pp 93-109; Pure Theory of Law pp 168-192
14
claims and duties. A corporation is distinct from one of its members when his conduct is governed not only by claims and duties, but also by a special set of rules which regulates his actions in relation to the other members of the corporation. It is this set of rules that constitutes the corporation. For example, whether the contract of an individual affects only him or the company of which he is a member will depend on whether or not the contract falls within the special set of rules regulating his actions in relation to his fellow members. This theory is also purely analytical and accurate as far as it goes. It omits the policy factors that bring about variations in the attitude of the courts, and it does not explain why the special set of rules, of which Kelsen spoke, is invoked in the case of corporations, but not in partnerships. In fairness to Kelsen it must be pointed out that he expressly disclaimed any desire to bring in the policy aspects of the law. All he was concerned to do was to present a formal picture of the law, and to that extent he did what he set out to do.
FICTION THEORY Its principal supporters are Savigny and Salmond.26 Juristic persons are only treated as if they are persons, ie human beings. It is thought that Sinibald Fieschi, who became Pope Innocent IV in 1243, was the first to employ the idea of persona ficta; 'cum collegium in causa universitatis fingatur una persona27'. It is clear that the theory presupposes that only human beings are 'properly' called 'persons'. Every single man and only the single man is capable of rights', declared Savigny28; and again, „The original concept of personality must coincide with the idea of man‟29. The theory appears to have originated during the Holy Roman Empire and at the height of Papal authority. Pope Innocent's statement may have been offered as the reason why ecclesiastical bodies could not be excommunicated or be capitally punished. All that the fiction theory asserts is that some groups and institutions are regarded as if they are persons and does not find it necessary to answer why. This gives it flexibility to enable it to accommodate the cases in English law where the mask is lifted and those where it is not, cases where groups are treated as persons for some purposes but not for 26
Salmond Jurisprudence 7th edition s 114
27
Gierke Das deutsche Genossenschaftsrecht III, 279 n 102
28
Savigny System des heutiden romischen Rechts II, 2-3
29
Savigny II, 60.
15
others. The popularity of this theory among English writers is explained partly by this very flexibility, partly by its avoidance of metaphysical notions of „mind‟ and 'will,' and partly by its nonpolitical character.
CONCESSION THEORY This is allied to the fiction theory and, in fact, supporters of the one tend also to support the other. Its main feature is that it regards the dignity of being a 'juristic person' as having to be conceded by the state, i.e. the law. The identification of 'law' with 'state' is necessary for this theory, but not for the fiction theory. It is a product of the era of the power of the national state, which superseded the Holy Roman Empire and in which the supremacy of the state was emphasised. It follows, therefore, that the concession theory has been used for political purposes to strengthen the state and to suppress autonomous bodies within it. No such body has any claim to recognition as a 'person.' It is a matter of discretion for the state. This is consistent with the deprivation of legal personality from outlaws; but on the other hand it is possible to argue that the common law corporations of English law discredit it somewhat though, even with these, there is a possibility of arguing that they are persons by virtue of a lost royal grant.
REALIST AND ORGANISM THEORY The 'realist' theory, of which Gierke is the principal exponent and Maitland a sympathizer30, asserts that 'juristic persons' enjoy a real existence as a group. A group tends to become a unit and to function as such. The theory is of German origin. Until the time of Bismarck, Germany consisted of a large number of separate states. Unification was their ideal, and the movement towards it assumed almost the character of a crusade. The very idea of unity and of collective working has never ceased to be something of a marvel, which may be one reason for the aura of mysticism and emotion which is seldom far from this theory. The „realist‟ theory opposes the concession theory.
30
Human beings are persons without any
Frederic William Maitland, The Collected Papers of Frederic William Maitland, ed. H.A.L. Fisher (Cambridge University Press, 1911). 3 Vols. Vol. 3. Chapter: THE CORPORATION SOLE 1 Accessed from on 20-02-2012
16
concession from the state and, so the argument runs, so far as groups are 'real,' they too are automatically persons. The 'organism' theory, with which the 'realist' theory is closely associated, asserts that groups are persons because they are 'organisms' and correspond biologically to human beings. This is based on a special use of the term 'organism' and the implications of such biological comparison can lead to absurdity31. It is said that they have a 'real life'. Professor Wolff points out that if this were true, a contract between two companies whereby one is to go into voluntary liquidation would be void as an agreement to commit suicide 32. It is also said that they have a 'group will' which is independent of the wills of its component members. Professor Wolff has pointed out that the 'group will' is only the result of mutually influenced wills33, which indeed every fictionist would admit. To say, on the other hand, that it is a single will is as much a fiction as ever the fictionists asserted. As Gray, quoting Windscheid, said, 'To get rid of the fiction of an attributed will, by saying that a corporation has a real general will, is to drive out one fiction by another34. It has also been stated that group entities are 'real' in a different sense from human beings. The 'reality' is physical, namely the unity of spirit, purpose, interests, and organisation. Even so, it fails to explain the inconsistencies of the law with regard to corporations. Connected with the realist theory is the 'Institutional' theory which marks a shift in emphasis from an individualist to a collectivist outlook. The individual is integrated into the institution and becomes part of it. The 'pluralist' form of this theory allowed the independent existence of many institutions within the supreme institution of the state. The 'fascist' form of it, however, gave it a twist so as to make the state the only institution, which integrated all others and allowed none to survive in an autonomous condition.
31
Discussed by Wollf pp 498-499. See, however, Denning LJ in HL Bolton (Engineering) co. Ltd. v TJ Graham and Sons Ltd. [1957] I QB 159 at 172, [1956] 3 All ER 624 at 630. A „realist‟ interpretation can be given to certain aspects of English Law, eg when a corporation is said to act, „personally‟ through its supreme directorate. Also Riverston Meat Co. Pty Ltd. v Lancashire Shipping Co. Ltd. [1961] AC 807 at 861, [1961] I All ER 495 at 516. 32
M. Wolff, “On the Nature of Legal Persons”, (1938) 54 Law Quarterly Review 494.
33
ibid.
34
Gray pp 54-55.
17
CHAPTER III CORPORATE PERSONALITY Classically, a corporation was conceived as an artificial person, coming into existence through creation by a sovereign power. Its primary business advantage, of course, was insulation of individual stockholders composing the corporation from liability for the debts of the corporate enterprise. The legal doctrine of corporate personality was built around the idea of a sovereign grant of certain attributes of personality to a definable group, engaged in an enterprise.35 SIR JOHN SALMOND‟S VIEWS ON CORPORATE PERSONALITY Salmond's views on corporate theory appear in Chapter XV of his Jurisprudence, which deals with Persons. Salmond's basic view was that "persons are the substances of which rights and duties are the attributes. It is only in this respect that persons possess juridical significance, and this is the exclusive point of view from which personality received legal recognition". He distinguished between natural and legal persons and said that legal persons are beings, real or imaginary, to whom the law attributes personality by way of fiction when there is none in fact. Although Salmond adopted the fiction theory he did so with certain reservations. He said that, although fictitious personality involves personification, the converse is not true. Personification in itself is a mere metaphor, not a legal fiction. "Legal personality is a definite legal conception; personification as such is a mere artifice of speech designed for compendious expression". People talk about a bench of judges or a partnership as a firm. This is simply metaphorical usage. A corporation is, on the other hand, a fictitious person representing a group of persons but is not identical with them. It is treated in law as a separate person. He followed the conventional distinction between corporations sole and aggregate. He thought that the chief difficulty in comprehending the true nature of a corporation sole is that it bears the same name as a natural person who is himself the sole member for the time being.
35
Adolf A. Berle, Jr, The Theory of Enterprise Entity, Columbia Law Review, Vol. 47, No. 3 (Apr., 1947), pp. 343-358
18
He acknowledged that while he accepted the generally received view that corporations are fictitious persons the theory has not gone unchallenged. He referred to the views of Gierke36 that the real Verbandspersonlichkeit is a group organism whose parts are human beings. He seemed to be aware of the problems of what Teubner has called "organicist collectivism".37 He drew attention to the fact that such a theory cannot accommodate the corporation sole and even in the case of a corporation aggregate "it seems impossible to admit that their personality is anything more than the outcome of metaphor and fiction". Salmond thought that although corporations are fictitious persons the acts, interests, rights and liabilities attributed to them by the law are those of natural persons. Otherwise the law of corporations would be destitute of any relation to actual fact. His attribution doctrine seems to have preceded that of Lord Hoffmann delivering the judgment of the Judicial Committee of the Privy Council in Meridian Global Funds Asia Ltd v Securities Commission.38
MAX WEBER‟S VIEWS ON CORPORATE PERSONALITY In the discussion on forms of creation of rights Weber deals with associational contracts.39 He sets out a useful historical survey of the evolution of juristic personality citing Gierke and Maitland. He emphasises that the concept of the juristic person from a legal standpoint is a tautology since the very concept of person is necessarily the juristic one. The determination of legal personality is just as artificial as the legal definition of "thing". That is, it is decided exclusively in accordance with selected juristic criteria. "The most rational actualisation of the idea of legal personality consists in the complete separation of the legal spheres of the members from the separately constituted legal sphere of the organisation." While certain persons designated according to rules are regarded from the legal point of view as alone authorised to assume obligations and acquire rights for the organisation, the legal relations
36
SJ Stoljar Groups and Entities: An Inquiry into Corporate Theory (ANU Press, Canberra, 1973) 183
37
Gunter Teubner "Enterprise Corporatism: New Industrial Policy and the 'Essence' of the Legal Person" in Sally Wheeler (ed) A Reader on the Law of the Business Enterprise (Oxford University Press, Oxford 1994) 51. 38
Meridian Global Funds Asia Ltd v Securities Commission [1995] 2 AC 500. See JH Farrar Corporate Governance: Theories, Principles and Practice (2 ed, Oxford University Press, Melbourne, 2004) ch 5. 39
Max Rheinstein (ed) Max Weber on Law and Economy and Society (Simon and Schuster, New York, 1954) 154.
19
thus created do not at all affect the members and their property but are imputed to a separate and distinct body of assets. Weber considered the institution of the State and whether this should be treated as a juristic person of private law. He analysed the position in Roman law and in Europe in the Middle Ages, drawing comparisons with England. He argued that the rational concept of the corporation in Roman law was a product of the imperial period, quite particularly the law of municipal corporations. It can be seen from the above that Weber's and Salmond's ideas are similar but Weber is richer in historical and comparative detail. The position with regard to corporations changed in the nineteenth century with the adoption of a more laissez faire approach to incorporation.40 CORPORATE PERSONALITY IN INDIA Coparcenary – As in Rome, so also in India, the concept of juristic personality was quite unknown, but the coparcenary system has however, been to a certain extent, familiar as a corporation. In this coparcenary system normally though each member is presumed to have certain rights, but the karta of the family is supreme in the management of the property and has control over the income and expenditure. He has absolute discretion in the management of the property and is entitled to spend the whole income even in spite of the objection of other members whose only remedy is to seek partition,41 if they are dissatisfied with his management. The karta of the joint family has not only been allowed to have extensive powers of alienating for value the joint family property but ,au also enter into a transaction in his own name where he may in turn have the power to sue and liability to be sued for that transaction. Other members of the family who are represented by the head are also bound by the decree.42 The coparcenary system of the Hindu law thus represents the true notion of corporation. Idols and Funds – Apart from the coparcenary system Idols and Funds under Hindu law have also been recognized as having legal personality. A Hindu idol is, according to long 40
Bouverie Speech on Second Reading of the Limited Liability Bill in the House of Commons (June 1855) 139 Hansard 310. 41
Bhawani v. Juggernath (1866) 3 Mad HC 177
42
Ramanatham v. SRMCTM (1937) Mad 880
20
established authority founded upon the religious customs of Hindus and the recognition thereof by the courts of law is a juristic entity.43 It has juridical status with the power of suing and liability of being sued. Its interests are attended to by the person who has the deity in his charge and who is in law its manager with all the powers which would in such circumstances on analogy being given to the manager of the estate of an infant heir. This is why the rules against perpetuity do not apply to endowments created in favour of an idol.
State as a Juristic Person – Of all forms of Human society the greatest is the State. It owns wealth in large quantity and performs functions which in number and importance are beyond all other associations. In modern times, it has been regarded as one of the greatest corporations ever known to law. It has been endowed with all powers to sue and liability to be sued.44 This is further strengthened by virtue of Art.300 of the Constitution of India. Besides this, there are many other provisions which clearly provide that the Union and State are legal persons. Part III dealing with Fundamental Rights puts numerous duties upon the state and provides at the same time for their enforcement by the Supreme Court and High Courts.45 Directive Principles of State Policy impose on State a duty to engraft laws as contained in those directions.
43
Pramath Nath Mullick v. Praduymna Kumar Mullick 52 IA 245
44
Shyam Sundar v. State of Rajasthan AIR 1974 SC 890
45
Art. 32 and Art. 226 of Constitution of India
21
CONCLUSION Firstly, no one explanation takes account of all aspects of the problem, and
criticism
becomes easy. Two questions should be kept clear: What does any theory set out to explain? and, What does one want a theory to explain? Those that have been considered are philosophical, political or analytical: they are not so much concerned with finding solutions to practical problems as with trying to explain the meaning of the word 'person'. Courts, on the other hand, faced with the solving of practical problems, have proceeded according to policy, not logic. The objectives of the law are not uniform. One of its main purposes in the case of human beings is to regulate behaviour; so there is, on the one hand, constant concern with the performance or non-performance of duties by individuals. With corporations the main purpose is to organise concerted activities and to ascribe collective responsibility therefore; so there is, on the other hand, emphasis on collective powers and liabilities. Secondly, as has been pointed out by more than one writer, English lawyers have not committed themselves to any theory. There is undoubtedly a good deal of theoretical speculation, but it is not easy to say how much of it affects actual decisions. Authority can sometimes be found in the same case to support different theories46. Thirdly, two linguistic fallacies appear to lie at the root of much of the theorising. One is that similarity of language form has masked shifts in meaning and dissimilarities in function. People speak of corporations in the same language that they use for human beings, but the word 'person' does not 'mean' the same in the two cases, either in point of what is referred to or function. The other fallacy is the persistent belief that words stand for things. Because the differences in function are obscured by the uniform language, this has led to some curious feats of argumentation to try and find some referent for the word 'person' when used in relation to corporation which is similar to the referent when the word is used in relation to human beings47. A glance at the development of the word persona, set out at the beginning of this chapter, shows progressiveness in the ideas represented by it. There is no 'essence' underlying the various uses of 'person'. The need to take account of the unity of a group and also to preserve flexibility are essential, but neither is tied to the word. 46
Pollock A first book of Jurisprudence pp 110-111; „Has the Common Law received the Fiction theory of Corporations?‟ in Essay in the Law p 151; Duff Personality in Roman Private Law. P 215. 47
Hart pp 49-59. Cf Auerbach „On Professor Hart‟s Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence‟ (1956) 9 Journal of Legal Education 39.
22
The application of it to human beings is something which the law shares with ordinary linguistic usage, although its connotation is slightly different, namely a unit of jural relations. Its application to things other than human beings is purely a matter of legal convenience. Neither the linguistic nor legal usages of 'person' are logical. If corporations aggregate are 'persons', then partnerships and trade unions should be too. The error lies in supposing that there should always be logic. Unless this has been understood, the varied uses of the word will only make it a confusing and emotional irritant.
23
REFERENCES ARTICLES 1. Adolf A. Berle, Jr, “The Theory of Enterprise Entity”, Columbia Law Review, Vol. 47, No. 3 (Apr., 1947), pp. 343-358 2. Bryant Smith, Legal Personality, The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 37, No. 3 (Jan., 1928), pp. 283-299 3. Fredrick Maitland, Corporation Sole, Law Quarterly Review, 16 (1900) pp. 335 -354 available at 4. Gunter Teubner "Enterprise Corporatism: New Industrial Policy and the 'Essence' of the Legal Person" in Sally Wheeler (ed) A Reader on the Law of the Business Enterprise (Oxford University Press, Oxford 1994) 51. 5. JH Farrar, “Corporate Governance: Theories, Principles and Practice” (2 ed, Oxford University Press, Melbourne, 2004) 6. John Finnis, The Priority of Persons available at:
7. M. Wolff, “On the Nature of Legal Persons”, (1938) 54 Law Quarterly Review 494. 8. SJ Stoljar, “Groups and Entities: An Inquiry into Corporate Theory” (ANU Press, Canberra, 1973) 183 9. Winfield “The Unborn Child” (1942) 5 Univ. Of Toronto Law Journal 278 at 279
BOOKS 1. Frederic William Maitland, The Collected Papers of Frederic William Maitland, ed. H.A.L. Fisher (Cambridge University Press, 1911). 2. Horace Gray, The Nature and Source of Law, (2nd Ed., 1921) pp. 27. 3. HLA Hart, Essays in jurisprudence and philosophy, Clarendon Press, (Reprint, 1983). 4. John Austin, Lectures on Jurisprudence, Campbell, London, (3rd ed, 1999) pp. 357358. 5. John William Salmond and Patrick John Fitzgerald, Salmond on Jurisprudence, Sweet & Maxwell, 1966 (12th Ed. 1966) pp. 231. 6. RWM Dias, Jurisprudence, Aditya Books Butterworths New Delhi (5th ed. 1994) pp. 250 – 270. 24
JUDICIAL DECISIONS 1. Bhawani v. Juggernath (1866) 3 Mad HC 177. 2. HL Bolton (Engineering) co. Ltd. v TJ Graham and Sons Ltd. [1957] I QB 159 at 172, [1956] 3 All ER 624 at 630. 3. Meridian Global Funds Asia Ltd v Securities Commission [1995] 2 AC 500. 4. Pramatha Nath Mullick v Pradyumna Nath Mullick (1925) LR 52 Ind App 245. 5. R v. Senior (1832) 1 Moody C.c. 344. 6. R v. West (1848) 2 Car. & Kir. 784. 7. Ramanatham v. SRMCTM (1937) Mad 880. 8. Re Luck‟s Settlement Truses, (1940) 1 Ch. 864 at p. 889. 9. Riverston Meat Co. Pty Ltd. v Lancashire Shipping Co. Ltd. [1961] AC 807 at 861, [1961] I All ER 495 at 516. 10. Shyam Sundar v. State of Rajasthan AIR 1974 SC 890. 11. Tagore v. Tagore (1872) Beng. LR 377.
Shyam Sunder and Ors. v. State of Rajasthan (AIR 1974 SC 890): Where the question of sovereign immunity was raised and reliance was placed on the ratio laid down in Kasturi Lal’s case (supra), this Court after considering the principle of sovereign immunity as understood in English and even applied in America observed that there was no ‘logical or practical’ ground for exempting the sovereign from the suit for damages. Meridian Global Funds Management Asia Ltd v Securities Commission
Meridian was part of a syndicate bidding to take over NZ company, Euro National Corp Ltd. Mr Koo and Mr Ng, working for Meridian, bought 49% of Euro’s shares. But Meridian failed to disclose to theSecurities Commission of New Zealand that they had become a ‘substantial security holder’ of over 5% because Koo and Ng wanted to hide the transaction from their superiors. The Commission imposed fines against Koo, Ng and the Meridian. The company argued it was not liable because it had not known about it. 25
Heron J held Meridian knew it was a substantial property holder, because as employees the knowledge of Koo and Ng was attributable to the company. The NZ Court of Appeal held that Koo’s knowledge should be attributable because he was the ‘directing mind and will’ of the company. Meridian argued that was only the board, not Koo. Lord Hoffmann for the Privy Council advised that ‘there would be little sense in deeming such a persona ficta to exist unless there were also rules to tell one what acts were to count as acts of the company. It is therefore a necessary part of corporate personality that there should be rules by which acts are attributed to the company. These may be called ‘the rules of attribution’. There can be rules in the constitution or rules implied (e.g. shareholders acting unanimously are the company, Multinational Gas). Otherwise, the principles of agency apply, and the company acts through its servants and agents.
26